In Roland Barthes’ first
chapter “The Photographic Message” in Image
Music Text, Barthes seeks to move beyond what sociology has primarily been
focused on with photographs, the source of emission (producer) and point of
reception (consumer), by directing our
attention to the channel of transmission (the text). He is interested in the connotative messages
images have, especially in the press photograph as such an image is accompanied
by a title, caption and article (as well as headlines). Barthes quickly identifies
that the newspaper, as a source of information, creates two different
structures ― linguistic in which the substance is words and visual/image in
which the substance is lines, shades, surfaces ― and that we must analyze both separately
in order to understand how each structure compliments the other. The
visual/image though is not an isolated structure; rather, such a text is
accompanied by a title, caption and article.
But, as Barthes suggests, producers, those sources of emissions (i.e. staff
of the newspaper: technicians who took the photo, others who choose, compose
and treat it, and those who give a caption, title, and commentary), of the
photograph often work to be “neutral” and “objective” in copying reality. A basic level of meaning, “message without a
code,” is evoked in the literal reality (although still manipulated by reductions
in proportions, perspective, color, etc.). The “neutrality” intention creates
sense of naturalness and eternalness, which will connect and be important for
the next layer of meanings. As Barthes continues to the other levels of
meanings ― “analogical reproductions of reality (drawings, paintings, cinema,
theater) and, more importantly, reception of the image, which in turn signifies
a certain ‘culture’ of the society receiving the message (17) ― he begins to
explore rhetoric, or the rhetorical dimensions of a text. A connoted system develops and “the code of
the connoted system is very likely constituted either by a universal symbolic
order or by a period rhetoric, in short by a stock of stereotypes (schemes,
colours, graphisms, gestures, expressions, arrangements of elements)” (18). My
first question was what rhetoric means for him. Is it simply a compilation of
stereotypes? A few paragraphs later, in
arguing that the status of the photograph has more than a denotation, he
suggests that the connotation provides a message with “a code (the ‘art’, or
the treatment, or the ‘writing’, or the rhetoric, of the photograph).” In other words, I gather that rhetoric means
a code, or the connotation, that deploys messages that are both “’objective’
and ‘invested’, natural and cultural” (20).
These messages are structured
by procedures, which are not part of the photographic structure, and Barthes
suggests six of them: trick effects, pose, objects, photogenia, aestheticism and
syntax. Barthes is concerned with the
first three, as “connotation is produced by a modification of the reality
itself” (21). In a trick effect
procedure, the connotation appears without warning, similar to what I thought
of as subverting the denotation, because of the particular historical
moment. The trick effect procedure is
done by the producer’s intent, and typically works as the beginning step in
naturalizing meanings. The pose
procedure is the content’s pose: the photo subject’s body position and parts
position. Barthes provides an example of
JFK, in which he has his eyes raised heavenwards, hands clasped in a
high-profile shot. Barthes suggests “youthfulness,
spirituality, purity” (22), although he doesn’t interrogate the image
much. I would have liked to see Barthes
unpack the image more, but that isn’t particularly his focus for the chapter (but
this is the reason why I think he shouldn’t even bring in a specific text if he
isn’t going to unpack). His next
procedure directs our attention to objects and Barthes emphasizes that objects
possess meaning and not power. This procedure is particularly interesting for me
and my indep. study in the fall with Dr. Gries.
While Barthes wants to focus on objects and their meanings, and I concur
with him, I also think power cannot be detached from meaning. Meanings produce power, as well as eradicate
power (I know I need to elaborate).
The object procedure also
reminded me of a conversation I had with my friend Kyle today about
consciousness and writing. It was an
interesting conversation and I won’t delve into all the details, but he did mention
something that relates to Barthes’ third procedure (objects) in connation in
images: memory. Kyle mentioned that we
have to write memories in order to produce memories and objects provide us with
a sense of memory. I brought up the idea
of objects possessing a memory in that we project consciousness onto objects
and give them a sense of consciousness. Kyle
fair warned me though that this may be problematic, and I agree, but I want to
clarify what I (think I) mean: a subject’s experience with an object, often and
almost always, evokes many different ideas, feelings, and narratives. The time a subject and object are together
will provide numerous opportunities to develop a narrative (which can easily be
fantasy or real). It will also give a
subject a consciousness (I know I’m throwing the word “consciousness” around
without any solid definition, which was also the issue Kyle and I were
discussing), as well as the object, although a different kind of,
consciousness. For example, a painting
on my living room has particular meanings for me. My friend Sandy painted it and offered it to
me at a particular moment in our lives. At the time of exchange, I had a
consciousness and set of meanings (friendship, gratitude, value of listening),
which all held shortly after (a couple of months). When she and I were no longer around each
other and the painting, I continued to have these particular ideas. These ideas
structure a memory. But did I have the ideas and memory or did the painting have
the ideas and memory? Sure, I could
think about Sandy and some of those ideas and the memory arose, but the ideas
and meanings were never as potent in my mind as they were when I looked at the
painting. In addition, I think the objects
absorbed meanings and develop a memory that was distinct. I’m unsure right now
what the object’s memory would be (i.e. would it be synonymous with my memory).
As the months passed, (as you might have noticed already by the past tense) the
meanings changed for me, as well as (I’m assuming) for the painting.
Now, let’s say the painting
gets damaged, maybe it falls off the wall, the glass breaks and the painting nearly
tears in two, and I have to throw it away.
I dispose of it in the dumpster in my parking lot and someone else finds
the painting. They decide to keep it,
maybe restore it or whatever, because it evokes certain meanings for this
person. Maybe the image evokes from
their memory sadness or joy or tranquility.
Now does the object’s consciousness change? Does the subject pack the object with new
meanings and a new memory? I would say yes because the context changed. The environment of the exchange with me and
Sandy, the traveling from Chicago to Gainesville, and my living room in Florida
all packed the painting. The breaking of the glass, the tearing of the
painting, and the travel of the painting to the dumpster packed a new set of
meanings (no value or reason in keeping or restoring the painting, my lack of
effective hanging, etc.). At the same time, the painting’s position in the
dumpster has a set of meanings for why it ended up in the dumpster. But those meanings and memories seem to be
lost with interjection of the other person and the painting absorbs new
meanings and memories. Of course, if you’ve reached this point in my writing,
my whole babble here is nearly meaningless without a definition of
consciousness and memory. Is
consciousness defined by memory? I have
always thought of consciousness as the ability to make meanings, as well as a
self awareness (which I know is loaded).
Possibly I need to rethink what consciousness is with attention to
memory. And maybe a definition of
consciousness is impossible as meanings are constantly fluid and shifting (as definitions
for words also do). And of course, I haven’t even discussed how writing
connects to this memory and object example, but I would like to explore further
some of these ideas.
I’ve also been thinking a lot
about visual rhetoric as it relates to multimodal composing, particularly in
the classroom. It would be impractical, as far as I know now, to have students
compose a visual essay, such as a 10 minute documentary. I cannot expect students to have the necessary
access to a video camera (although they probably have video cameras on their
phone) and an editing program. However,
in 1102 last semester, we had students do visual maps, where they had to design
a visual representation of their research sources. The idea was to have students demonstrate the
complexity of weaving together sources, as well as aid students in organizing
their papers. I thought it was an interesting assignment. As a way for students to begin thinking
visually about their research and their research paper, on one my lectures days,
I showed the video on Ken Robinson’s paper on “Changing Education Paradigms” (http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=zDZFcDGpL4U). After the ten minute video, I busted out
colored pencils and sheets of paper and asked students, with their five
annotations from their annotated bibliography, to represent visually the
conversation of their sources, as well as their own position around their
topic. Students seemed to really enjoy
the activity and many mentioned it gave them a different way of thinking about
their topic and argument. I wonder if we (teachers) had spent some more time in
discussing visual rhetoric, specifically production and invention, would
students be able to create a much different argument in the end A nascent idea, but something I wish to
explore more in the next couple of weeks.
Barthes, Roland. Image Music
Text. Trans. Stephen Heath. New York: Hill and Wang, 1977. Print.
If consciousness is operationally closed (to use systems theory terms) in the sense that we cannot "transfer" consciousness to an object or "express" what is in our consciousness, then we are left with the idea that the painting, for instance, may be a catalyst for changing your state of mind or for triggering certain memories that you have, but these memories wouldn't be part of the object's "consciousness." I haven't read this Barthes essay in awhile and have no way to currently access this, but I'm not sure what distinction you (/Barthes) is making between objects and pose; Is the "object" the content of the image, or the image in its materiality?
ReplyDeleteThat said, you bring up an interesting question about the relationship between what we might think of as "personal" meaning and "public" meaning (a tenuous distinctions that I think Barthes probably wouldn't maintain). I can't remember if its in Camera Lucida or Image, Music, Text but Barthes makes a distinction (although this distinction, again, is not hard and fast) between the "studium" and the "punctum" -- the "studium" is associated with cultural meanings-- all of the interpretations we make of an image that we could probably explain to another and they would understand what we mean. The "punctum," by contrast, is something in the image that "pricks" or "stings" the viewer. It is something that, in a certain sense, cannot be communicated, so it is not the external narrative that we might form around, say, the painting that you mention--because you can explain through that narrative and through common notions why that painting would be significant in your life; This is why the punctum/studium distinction is so problematic -- Barthes variously tries to describe the punctum as a "little detail" that is already IN the photograph and yet that we "add" to it as well - but this has nothing to do with a "consciousness" of the photograph/image.
These reflections are incomplete and I wish I had my copy of Barthes with me to cite my references and refer to particular passages.